About the relationship between non-termination and inconsistency?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
5
down vote

favorite
2












I've been trying to get into Agda and I noticed that it doesn't have recursion, which implies that it isn't Turing-Complete.



From what I could understand, if Agda had recursion, it would make itself an inconsistency from a type theory perspective.



Something stuck to my mind: Is it possible to exist a language that it isn't strongly normalizing but, yet, consistent? Or does the existence of recursion mandatorily implies inconsistency?










share|cite|improve this question



















  • 2




    Forcibly add a reduction rule $t to t$, and normalization is lost, but all the logical properties are preserved :)
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 16:50










  • Thank you for the answer, chi. However, I'm having a hard time wrapping my head around it, would it be possible for you to expand your answer a little?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 17:31







  • 2




    Done. I don't think my answer will be really satisfactory, but at least it points out a few trivial cases.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 17:41














up vote
5
down vote

favorite
2












I've been trying to get into Agda and I noticed that it doesn't have recursion, which implies that it isn't Turing-Complete.



From what I could understand, if Agda had recursion, it would make itself an inconsistency from a type theory perspective.



Something stuck to my mind: Is it possible to exist a language that it isn't strongly normalizing but, yet, consistent? Or does the existence of recursion mandatorily implies inconsistency?










share|cite|improve this question



















  • 2




    Forcibly add a reduction rule $t to t$, and normalization is lost, but all the logical properties are preserved :)
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 16:50










  • Thank you for the answer, chi. However, I'm having a hard time wrapping my head around it, would it be possible for you to expand your answer a little?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 17:31







  • 2




    Done. I don't think my answer will be really satisfactory, but at least it points out a few trivial cases.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 17:41












up vote
5
down vote

favorite
2









up vote
5
down vote

favorite
2






2





I've been trying to get into Agda and I noticed that it doesn't have recursion, which implies that it isn't Turing-Complete.



From what I could understand, if Agda had recursion, it would make itself an inconsistency from a type theory perspective.



Something stuck to my mind: Is it possible to exist a language that it isn't strongly normalizing but, yet, consistent? Or does the existence of recursion mandatorily implies inconsistency?










share|cite|improve this question















I've been trying to get into Agda and I noticed that it doesn't have recursion, which implies that it isn't Turing-Complete.



From what I could understand, if Agda had recursion, it would make itself an inconsistency from a type theory perspective.



Something stuck to my mind: Is it possible to exist a language that it isn't strongly normalizing but, yet, consistent? Or does the existence of recursion mandatorily implies inconsistency?







formal-languages functional-programming






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Sep 27 at 16:33

























asked Sep 27 at 16:22









Tiago Loriato Simões

284




284







  • 2




    Forcibly add a reduction rule $t to t$, and normalization is lost, but all the logical properties are preserved :)
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 16:50










  • Thank you for the answer, chi. However, I'm having a hard time wrapping my head around it, would it be possible for you to expand your answer a little?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 17:31







  • 2




    Done. I don't think my answer will be really satisfactory, but at least it points out a few trivial cases.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 17:41












  • 2




    Forcibly add a reduction rule $t to t$, and normalization is lost, but all the logical properties are preserved :)
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 16:50










  • Thank you for the answer, chi. However, I'm having a hard time wrapping my head around it, would it be possible for you to expand your answer a little?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 17:31







  • 2




    Done. I don't think my answer will be really satisfactory, but at least it points out a few trivial cases.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 17:41







2




2




Forcibly add a reduction rule $t to t$, and normalization is lost, but all the logical properties are preserved :)
– chi
Sep 27 at 16:50




Forcibly add a reduction rule $t to t$, and normalization is lost, but all the logical properties are preserved :)
– chi
Sep 27 at 16:50












Thank you for the answer, chi. However, I'm having a hard time wrapping my head around it, would it be possible for you to expand your answer a little?
– Tiago Loriato Simões
Sep 27 at 17:31





Thank you for the answer, chi. However, I'm having a hard time wrapping my head around it, would it be possible for you to expand your answer a little?
– Tiago Loriato Simões
Sep 27 at 17:31





2




2




Done. I don't think my answer will be really satisfactory, but at least it points out a few trivial cases.
– chi
Sep 27 at 17:41




Done. I don't think my answer will be really satisfactory, but at least it points out a few trivial cases.
– chi
Sep 27 at 17:41










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
4
down vote



accepted










Some trivial type systems



Let the set of types be $bot,top$ and the sets of terms be $a,b$, with typing rules



$$
vdash a:top qquad vdash b:top
$$

and computational rules
$$
a to b qquad b to a
$$



Then, the resulting system has no (weakly/strongly) normalizing terms, yet it is consistent since no term inhabits $bot$.



We can also allow recursion on $top$, if we want.



$$
dfrac
Gamma, x:top vdash e:top

Gamma vdash sf rec x. e :top

$$

with the obvious computational rule
$$
sf rec x. e to esf rec x. e/x
$$



On adding full recursion



Of course, we can't allow unrestricted recursion on $bot$, otherwise $sf rec x.x:bot$ leads to an inconsistency.



Adapting more serious type systems



If we take any strongly normalizing typed lambda calculus, we can modify the computational rules to add a silly reduction step
$$
tto t
$$

for any term $t$.



The new calculus has as inhabited types the same inhabited types, so it preserves consistency. The calculus is not even weakly normalizing, though.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • That was extremely useful! Since there are so many simple ways of adding non-normalized terms without leading to an inconsistency, why is it such a big deal for Agda? Is there an explanation for the cause of this problem?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 18:06







  • 2




    @TiagoLoriatoSimoes With a powerful calculus like Agda, without normalization it can be hard to prove consistency. The $tto t$ rule above is simple to handle, but adding a constrained form of non-always-terminating recursion can be vastly more complex. Also, it is nice to know that when you prove in Agda that there is some natural satisfying some property, you get for free a terminating program which produces said natural. That's one of the main features of constructivism, and people don't want to break that.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 18:20






  • 1




    I think your trivial type system might be too trivial. In particular, usually recursion principles allow an arbitrary target type, and you have suggested here that avoiding recursion into bottom solves the problem, but this only works because there are only two types and we know which ones are supposed to be inhabited. In any reasonable type system with empty types, it is not decidable to determine if a type is empty, so this doesn't work.
    – Mario Carneiro
    Sep 27 at 22:18







  • 1




    @chi You have to be careful with that kind of $mathrmfix$: taking $n=mathrmfix mathrmnat 0 S$, with the appropriate computational rules on $mathrmfix$, you should be able to prove $n=S n$, which implies a contradiction! It isn't enough to restrict fixed points to inhabited types: they must also have a consistent semantics. In Agda, natural numbers are definite, i.e. they must have a precisely defined value in terms of the constructors.
    – cody
    Sep 28 at 14:39






  • 1




    @MarioCarneiro The point is, in Agda using a inductive naturals type $sf nat$, you can prove $forall x:sf nat. xneq S x$. This copes with the counterexample by cody: $x=sf fix nat 0 S : sf nat$
    – chi
    Sep 28 at 20:44











Your Answer




StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "419"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: false,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: null,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fcs.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f97836%2fabout-the-relationship-between-non-termination-and-inconsistency%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
4
down vote



accepted










Some trivial type systems



Let the set of types be $bot,top$ and the sets of terms be $a,b$, with typing rules



$$
vdash a:top qquad vdash b:top
$$

and computational rules
$$
a to b qquad b to a
$$



Then, the resulting system has no (weakly/strongly) normalizing terms, yet it is consistent since no term inhabits $bot$.



We can also allow recursion on $top$, if we want.



$$
dfrac
Gamma, x:top vdash e:top

Gamma vdash sf rec x. e :top

$$

with the obvious computational rule
$$
sf rec x. e to esf rec x. e/x
$$



On adding full recursion



Of course, we can't allow unrestricted recursion on $bot$, otherwise $sf rec x.x:bot$ leads to an inconsistency.



Adapting more serious type systems



If we take any strongly normalizing typed lambda calculus, we can modify the computational rules to add a silly reduction step
$$
tto t
$$

for any term $t$.



The new calculus has as inhabited types the same inhabited types, so it preserves consistency. The calculus is not even weakly normalizing, though.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • That was extremely useful! Since there are so many simple ways of adding non-normalized terms without leading to an inconsistency, why is it such a big deal for Agda? Is there an explanation for the cause of this problem?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 18:06







  • 2




    @TiagoLoriatoSimoes With a powerful calculus like Agda, without normalization it can be hard to prove consistency. The $tto t$ rule above is simple to handle, but adding a constrained form of non-always-terminating recursion can be vastly more complex. Also, it is nice to know that when you prove in Agda that there is some natural satisfying some property, you get for free a terminating program which produces said natural. That's one of the main features of constructivism, and people don't want to break that.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 18:20






  • 1




    I think your trivial type system might be too trivial. In particular, usually recursion principles allow an arbitrary target type, and you have suggested here that avoiding recursion into bottom solves the problem, but this only works because there are only two types and we know which ones are supposed to be inhabited. In any reasonable type system with empty types, it is not decidable to determine if a type is empty, so this doesn't work.
    – Mario Carneiro
    Sep 27 at 22:18







  • 1




    @chi You have to be careful with that kind of $mathrmfix$: taking $n=mathrmfix mathrmnat 0 S$, with the appropriate computational rules on $mathrmfix$, you should be able to prove $n=S n$, which implies a contradiction! It isn't enough to restrict fixed points to inhabited types: they must also have a consistent semantics. In Agda, natural numbers are definite, i.e. they must have a precisely defined value in terms of the constructors.
    – cody
    Sep 28 at 14:39






  • 1




    @MarioCarneiro The point is, in Agda using a inductive naturals type $sf nat$, you can prove $forall x:sf nat. xneq S x$. This copes with the counterexample by cody: $x=sf fix nat 0 S : sf nat$
    – chi
    Sep 28 at 20:44















up vote
4
down vote



accepted










Some trivial type systems



Let the set of types be $bot,top$ and the sets of terms be $a,b$, with typing rules



$$
vdash a:top qquad vdash b:top
$$

and computational rules
$$
a to b qquad b to a
$$



Then, the resulting system has no (weakly/strongly) normalizing terms, yet it is consistent since no term inhabits $bot$.



We can also allow recursion on $top$, if we want.



$$
dfrac
Gamma, x:top vdash e:top

Gamma vdash sf rec x. e :top

$$

with the obvious computational rule
$$
sf rec x. e to esf rec x. e/x
$$



On adding full recursion



Of course, we can't allow unrestricted recursion on $bot$, otherwise $sf rec x.x:bot$ leads to an inconsistency.



Adapting more serious type systems



If we take any strongly normalizing typed lambda calculus, we can modify the computational rules to add a silly reduction step
$$
tto t
$$

for any term $t$.



The new calculus has as inhabited types the same inhabited types, so it preserves consistency. The calculus is not even weakly normalizing, though.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • That was extremely useful! Since there are so many simple ways of adding non-normalized terms without leading to an inconsistency, why is it such a big deal for Agda? Is there an explanation for the cause of this problem?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 18:06







  • 2




    @TiagoLoriatoSimoes With a powerful calculus like Agda, without normalization it can be hard to prove consistency. The $tto t$ rule above is simple to handle, but adding a constrained form of non-always-terminating recursion can be vastly more complex. Also, it is nice to know that when you prove in Agda that there is some natural satisfying some property, you get for free a terminating program which produces said natural. That's one of the main features of constructivism, and people don't want to break that.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 18:20






  • 1




    I think your trivial type system might be too trivial. In particular, usually recursion principles allow an arbitrary target type, and you have suggested here that avoiding recursion into bottom solves the problem, but this only works because there are only two types and we know which ones are supposed to be inhabited. In any reasonable type system with empty types, it is not decidable to determine if a type is empty, so this doesn't work.
    – Mario Carneiro
    Sep 27 at 22:18







  • 1




    @chi You have to be careful with that kind of $mathrmfix$: taking $n=mathrmfix mathrmnat 0 S$, with the appropriate computational rules on $mathrmfix$, you should be able to prove $n=S n$, which implies a contradiction! It isn't enough to restrict fixed points to inhabited types: they must also have a consistent semantics. In Agda, natural numbers are definite, i.e. they must have a precisely defined value in terms of the constructors.
    – cody
    Sep 28 at 14:39






  • 1




    @MarioCarneiro The point is, in Agda using a inductive naturals type $sf nat$, you can prove $forall x:sf nat. xneq S x$. This copes with the counterexample by cody: $x=sf fix nat 0 S : sf nat$
    – chi
    Sep 28 at 20:44













up vote
4
down vote



accepted







up vote
4
down vote



accepted






Some trivial type systems



Let the set of types be $bot,top$ and the sets of terms be $a,b$, with typing rules



$$
vdash a:top qquad vdash b:top
$$

and computational rules
$$
a to b qquad b to a
$$



Then, the resulting system has no (weakly/strongly) normalizing terms, yet it is consistent since no term inhabits $bot$.



We can also allow recursion on $top$, if we want.



$$
dfrac
Gamma, x:top vdash e:top

Gamma vdash sf rec x. e :top

$$

with the obvious computational rule
$$
sf rec x. e to esf rec x. e/x
$$



On adding full recursion



Of course, we can't allow unrestricted recursion on $bot$, otherwise $sf rec x.x:bot$ leads to an inconsistency.



Adapting more serious type systems



If we take any strongly normalizing typed lambda calculus, we can modify the computational rules to add a silly reduction step
$$
tto t
$$

for any term $t$.



The new calculus has as inhabited types the same inhabited types, so it preserves consistency. The calculus is not even weakly normalizing, though.






share|cite|improve this answer














Some trivial type systems



Let the set of types be $bot,top$ and the sets of terms be $a,b$, with typing rules



$$
vdash a:top qquad vdash b:top
$$

and computational rules
$$
a to b qquad b to a
$$



Then, the resulting system has no (weakly/strongly) normalizing terms, yet it is consistent since no term inhabits $bot$.



We can also allow recursion on $top$, if we want.



$$
dfrac
Gamma, x:top vdash e:top

Gamma vdash sf rec x. e :top

$$

with the obvious computational rule
$$
sf rec x. e to esf rec x. e/x
$$



On adding full recursion



Of course, we can't allow unrestricted recursion on $bot$, otherwise $sf rec x.x:bot$ leads to an inconsistency.



Adapting more serious type systems



If we take any strongly normalizing typed lambda calculus, we can modify the computational rules to add a silly reduction step
$$
tto t
$$

for any term $t$.



The new calculus has as inhabited types the same inhabited types, so it preserves consistency. The calculus is not even weakly normalizing, though.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Sep 27 at 20:58

























answered Sep 27 at 17:31









chi

10.7k1628




10.7k1628











  • That was extremely useful! Since there are so many simple ways of adding non-normalized terms without leading to an inconsistency, why is it such a big deal for Agda? Is there an explanation for the cause of this problem?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 18:06







  • 2




    @TiagoLoriatoSimoes With a powerful calculus like Agda, without normalization it can be hard to prove consistency. The $tto t$ rule above is simple to handle, but adding a constrained form of non-always-terminating recursion can be vastly more complex. Also, it is nice to know that when you prove in Agda that there is some natural satisfying some property, you get for free a terminating program which produces said natural. That's one of the main features of constructivism, and people don't want to break that.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 18:20






  • 1




    I think your trivial type system might be too trivial. In particular, usually recursion principles allow an arbitrary target type, and you have suggested here that avoiding recursion into bottom solves the problem, but this only works because there are only two types and we know which ones are supposed to be inhabited. In any reasonable type system with empty types, it is not decidable to determine if a type is empty, so this doesn't work.
    – Mario Carneiro
    Sep 27 at 22:18







  • 1




    @chi You have to be careful with that kind of $mathrmfix$: taking $n=mathrmfix mathrmnat 0 S$, with the appropriate computational rules on $mathrmfix$, you should be able to prove $n=S n$, which implies a contradiction! It isn't enough to restrict fixed points to inhabited types: they must also have a consistent semantics. In Agda, natural numbers are definite, i.e. they must have a precisely defined value in terms of the constructors.
    – cody
    Sep 28 at 14:39






  • 1




    @MarioCarneiro The point is, in Agda using a inductive naturals type $sf nat$, you can prove $forall x:sf nat. xneq S x$. This copes with the counterexample by cody: $x=sf fix nat 0 S : sf nat$
    – chi
    Sep 28 at 20:44

















  • That was extremely useful! Since there are so many simple ways of adding non-normalized terms without leading to an inconsistency, why is it such a big deal for Agda? Is there an explanation for the cause of this problem?
    – Tiago Loriato Simões
    Sep 27 at 18:06







  • 2




    @TiagoLoriatoSimoes With a powerful calculus like Agda, without normalization it can be hard to prove consistency. The $tto t$ rule above is simple to handle, but adding a constrained form of non-always-terminating recursion can be vastly more complex. Also, it is nice to know that when you prove in Agda that there is some natural satisfying some property, you get for free a terminating program which produces said natural. That's one of the main features of constructivism, and people don't want to break that.
    – chi
    Sep 27 at 18:20






  • 1




    I think your trivial type system might be too trivial. In particular, usually recursion principles allow an arbitrary target type, and you have suggested here that avoiding recursion into bottom solves the problem, but this only works because there are only two types and we know which ones are supposed to be inhabited. In any reasonable type system with empty types, it is not decidable to determine if a type is empty, so this doesn't work.
    – Mario Carneiro
    Sep 27 at 22:18







  • 1




    @chi You have to be careful with that kind of $mathrmfix$: taking $n=mathrmfix mathrmnat 0 S$, with the appropriate computational rules on $mathrmfix$, you should be able to prove $n=S n$, which implies a contradiction! It isn't enough to restrict fixed points to inhabited types: they must also have a consistent semantics. In Agda, natural numbers are definite, i.e. they must have a precisely defined value in terms of the constructors.
    – cody
    Sep 28 at 14:39






  • 1




    @MarioCarneiro The point is, in Agda using a inductive naturals type $sf nat$, you can prove $forall x:sf nat. xneq S x$. This copes with the counterexample by cody: $x=sf fix nat 0 S : sf nat$
    – chi
    Sep 28 at 20:44
















That was extremely useful! Since there are so many simple ways of adding non-normalized terms without leading to an inconsistency, why is it such a big deal for Agda? Is there an explanation for the cause of this problem?
– Tiago Loriato Simões
Sep 27 at 18:06





That was extremely useful! Since there are so many simple ways of adding non-normalized terms without leading to an inconsistency, why is it such a big deal for Agda? Is there an explanation for the cause of this problem?
– Tiago Loriato Simões
Sep 27 at 18:06





2




2




@TiagoLoriatoSimoes With a powerful calculus like Agda, without normalization it can be hard to prove consistency. The $tto t$ rule above is simple to handle, but adding a constrained form of non-always-terminating recursion can be vastly more complex. Also, it is nice to know that when you prove in Agda that there is some natural satisfying some property, you get for free a terminating program which produces said natural. That's one of the main features of constructivism, and people don't want to break that.
– chi
Sep 27 at 18:20




@TiagoLoriatoSimoes With a powerful calculus like Agda, without normalization it can be hard to prove consistency. The $tto t$ rule above is simple to handle, but adding a constrained form of non-always-terminating recursion can be vastly more complex. Also, it is nice to know that when you prove in Agda that there is some natural satisfying some property, you get for free a terminating program which produces said natural. That's one of the main features of constructivism, and people don't want to break that.
– chi
Sep 27 at 18:20




1




1




I think your trivial type system might be too trivial. In particular, usually recursion principles allow an arbitrary target type, and you have suggested here that avoiding recursion into bottom solves the problem, but this only works because there are only two types and we know which ones are supposed to be inhabited. In any reasonable type system with empty types, it is not decidable to determine if a type is empty, so this doesn't work.
– Mario Carneiro
Sep 27 at 22:18





I think your trivial type system might be too trivial. In particular, usually recursion principles allow an arbitrary target type, and you have suggested here that avoiding recursion into bottom solves the problem, but this only works because there are only two types and we know which ones are supposed to be inhabited. In any reasonable type system with empty types, it is not decidable to determine if a type is empty, so this doesn't work.
– Mario Carneiro
Sep 27 at 22:18





1




1




@chi You have to be careful with that kind of $mathrmfix$: taking $n=mathrmfix mathrmnat 0 S$, with the appropriate computational rules on $mathrmfix$, you should be able to prove $n=S n$, which implies a contradiction! It isn't enough to restrict fixed points to inhabited types: they must also have a consistent semantics. In Agda, natural numbers are definite, i.e. they must have a precisely defined value in terms of the constructors.
– cody
Sep 28 at 14:39




@chi You have to be careful with that kind of $mathrmfix$: taking $n=mathrmfix mathrmnat 0 S$, with the appropriate computational rules on $mathrmfix$, you should be able to prove $n=S n$, which implies a contradiction! It isn't enough to restrict fixed points to inhabited types: they must also have a consistent semantics. In Agda, natural numbers are definite, i.e. they must have a precisely defined value in terms of the constructors.
– cody
Sep 28 at 14:39




1




1




@MarioCarneiro The point is, in Agda using a inductive naturals type $sf nat$, you can prove $forall x:sf nat. xneq S x$. This copes with the counterexample by cody: $x=sf fix nat 0 S : sf nat$
– chi
Sep 28 at 20:44





@MarioCarneiro The point is, in Agda using a inductive naturals type $sf nat$, you can prove $forall x:sf nat. xneq S x$. This copes with the counterexample by cody: $x=sf fix nat 0 S : sf nat$
– chi
Sep 28 at 20:44


















 

draft saved


draft discarded















































 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fcs.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f97836%2fabout-the-relationship-between-non-termination-and-inconsistency%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Popular posts from this blog

How to check contact read email or not when send email to Individual?

Bahrain

Postfix configuration issue with fips on centos 7; mailgun relay