What is an example of a proof by minimal counterexample?
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
up vote
7
down vote
favorite
I was reading about proof by infinite descent, and proof by minimal counterexample. My understanding of it is that we assume the existance of some smallest counterexample $A$ that disproves some proposition $P$, then go onto show that there is some smaller counterexample to this which to me seems like a mix of infinite descent and 'reverse proof by contradiction'.
My question is, how do we know that there might be some counterexample? Furthermore, are there any examples of this?
proof-writing examples-counterexamples infinite-descent
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
7
down vote
favorite
I was reading about proof by infinite descent, and proof by minimal counterexample. My understanding of it is that we assume the existance of some smallest counterexample $A$ that disproves some proposition $P$, then go onto show that there is some smaller counterexample to this which to me seems like a mix of infinite descent and 'reverse proof by contradiction'.
My question is, how do we know that there might be some counterexample? Furthermore, are there any examples of this?
proof-writing examples-counterexamples infinite-descent
3
If there aren't any counterexamples, the theorem is true, and we're done, so it's only the case where there is a counterexample that we have to deal with. This method of proof goes back (at least) to Fermat, who called it "proof by infinite descent." Google that, and you'll find lots of examples.
– saulspatz
Nov 17 at 19:14
Related: matheducators.stackexchange.com/questions/10021/…
– Ethan Bolker
Nov 17 at 19:25
1
Any uneven natural number is prime. Counterexample 9 = 3*3.
– Uwe
Nov 17 at 21:52
Are you referring to things like i.stack.imgur.com/RxeiH.png?
– forest
2 days ago
2
(If I understand correctly) "proof by minimal counterexample" proves that a minimal counterexample does not exist (wikipedia), and the 2 comments above are not correct.
– user202729
2 days ago
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
7
down vote
favorite
up vote
7
down vote
favorite
I was reading about proof by infinite descent, and proof by minimal counterexample. My understanding of it is that we assume the existance of some smallest counterexample $A$ that disproves some proposition $P$, then go onto show that there is some smaller counterexample to this which to me seems like a mix of infinite descent and 'reverse proof by contradiction'.
My question is, how do we know that there might be some counterexample? Furthermore, are there any examples of this?
proof-writing examples-counterexamples infinite-descent
I was reading about proof by infinite descent, and proof by minimal counterexample. My understanding of it is that we assume the existance of some smallest counterexample $A$ that disproves some proposition $P$, then go onto show that there is some smaller counterexample to this which to me seems like a mix of infinite descent and 'reverse proof by contradiction'.
My question is, how do we know that there might be some counterexample? Furthermore, are there any examples of this?
proof-writing examples-counterexamples infinite-descent
proof-writing examples-counterexamples infinite-descent
edited Nov 17 at 22:00
José Carlos Santos
139k18111203
139k18111203
asked Nov 17 at 19:09
Jonathan Low
465
465
3
If there aren't any counterexamples, the theorem is true, and we're done, so it's only the case where there is a counterexample that we have to deal with. This method of proof goes back (at least) to Fermat, who called it "proof by infinite descent." Google that, and you'll find lots of examples.
– saulspatz
Nov 17 at 19:14
Related: matheducators.stackexchange.com/questions/10021/…
– Ethan Bolker
Nov 17 at 19:25
1
Any uneven natural number is prime. Counterexample 9 = 3*3.
– Uwe
Nov 17 at 21:52
Are you referring to things like i.stack.imgur.com/RxeiH.png?
– forest
2 days ago
2
(If I understand correctly) "proof by minimal counterexample" proves that a minimal counterexample does not exist (wikipedia), and the 2 comments above are not correct.
– user202729
2 days ago
|
show 1 more comment
3
If there aren't any counterexamples, the theorem is true, and we're done, so it's only the case where there is a counterexample that we have to deal with. This method of proof goes back (at least) to Fermat, who called it "proof by infinite descent." Google that, and you'll find lots of examples.
– saulspatz
Nov 17 at 19:14
Related: matheducators.stackexchange.com/questions/10021/…
– Ethan Bolker
Nov 17 at 19:25
1
Any uneven natural number is prime. Counterexample 9 = 3*3.
– Uwe
Nov 17 at 21:52
Are you referring to things like i.stack.imgur.com/RxeiH.png?
– forest
2 days ago
2
(If I understand correctly) "proof by minimal counterexample" proves that a minimal counterexample does not exist (wikipedia), and the 2 comments above are not correct.
– user202729
2 days ago
3
3
If there aren't any counterexamples, the theorem is true, and we're done, so it's only the case where there is a counterexample that we have to deal with. This method of proof goes back (at least) to Fermat, who called it "proof by infinite descent." Google that, and you'll find lots of examples.
– saulspatz
Nov 17 at 19:14
If there aren't any counterexamples, the theorem is true, and we're done, so it's only the case where there is a counterexample that we have to deal with. This method of proof goes back (at least) to Fermat, who called it "proof by infinite descent." Google that, and you'll find lots of examples.
– saulspatz
Nov 17 at 19:14
Related: matheducators.stackexchange.com/questions/10021/…
– Ethan Bolker
Nov 17 at 19:25
Related: matheducators.stackexchange.com/questions/10021/…
– Ethan Bolker
Nov 17 at 19:25
1
1
Any uneven natural number is prime. Counterexample 9 = 3*3.
– Uwe
Nov 17 at 21:52
Any uneven natural number is prime. Counterexample 9 = 3*3.
– Uwe
Nov 17 at 21:52
Are you referring to things like i.stack.imgur.com/RxeiH.png?
– forest
2 days ago
Are you referring to things like i.stack.imgur.com/RxeiH.png?
– forest
2 days ago
2
2
(If I understand correctly) "proof by minimal counterexample" proves that a minimal counterexample does not exist (wikipedia), and the 2 comments above are not correct.
– user202729
2 days ago
(If I understand correctly) "proof by minimal counterexample" proves that a minimal counterexample does not exist (wikipedia), and the 2 comments above are not correct.
– user202729
2 days ago
|
show 1 more comment
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
up vote
22
down vote
accepted
Consider, for instance, the statment: every $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ can be written as a product of prime numbers (including the case in which there's a single prime number appearing only once). Suppose otherwise. Then there would be a smallest $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ that would not be possible the express as a product of prime numbers. In particular, this implies that $n$ cannot be a prime number. Since $n$ is also not $1$, it can be written as $atimes b$, where $a,bin2,3,ldots,n-1$. But, since $n$ is the smallest counterexample, neither $a$ nor $b$ are counterexamples and therefore both of them can be written as a product of prime numbers. But then $n(=atimes b)$ can be written in such a way too.
add a comment |
up vote
13
down vote
Such a proof will often go as follows.
- Assume for contradiction that there is a counterexample to $P$ within some well-ordered set $X$.
- Consider the (certainly non-empty) set of all $X$ which are counterexamples to $P$. This set has a least element (that's what it means to be a well-order), so…
- Consider the smallest counterexample.
- Show that you can find a smaller counterexample.
- Contradiction, so there can't have been any counterexamples to $P$ after all.
- Therefore $P$ is true.
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
Assume the $sqrt2$ is rational then there are whole numbers $(a,b)$ such that $sqrt2=a/b$ and $a$ is the smallest number with this property but then we find that $a/2, b/2$ are also whole numbers with this property. So there is a smaller example.
I think this must be the example people are the most familiar with and it's a kind of infinite descent even though we often don't refer to it as such.
1
In this proof how do we know that $a/2$, $b/2$ are also whole numbers? (I'm probably missing something obvious.)
– LarsH
Nov 18 at 0:50
1
It isn't obvious but it is infamous. I can't find it for you now because I am out to dinner. But you can find by looking up the classic proof regarding the irrationality of square root of 2. Its in Bertrand Russell's history of western philosophy...
– Mason
Nov 18 at 0:57
3
@LarsH ny squaring the equation and wiggling it a bit you can prove that a is even, and then that b is also even.
– Dan M.
Nov 18 at 2:29
Here are the details
– Mason
Nov 18 at 2:38
1
@LarsH We have $2 = a^2/b^2$ hence $2b^2 = a^2$ from which: $a^2$ is even, hence $a$ is even, hence $a^2$ is a multiple of 4, hence $b^2=a^2/2$ is even, hence $b$ is even. So, both $a,b$ are even.
– chi
2 days ago
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
A fundamental example in number theory is descent by (Euclidean) division with remainder (or, equivalently, by repeated subtraction), as in the following basic result.
Lemma $ $ Let $,S,$ be a nonempty set of positive integers that is closed under subtraction $> 0,,$ i.e. for all $ ,n,min S, ,$ $ n > m Rightarrow n-m, in, S.,$ Then the least $ :ellin S,$ divides every element of $, S.$
Proof $bf 1, $ If not there is a least nonmultiple $ ,nin S,,$ contra $ ,n-ell in S,$ is a nonmultiple of $ ,ell.$
Proof $bf 2, , S,$ closed under subtraction $ ,Rightarrow,S,$ closed under remainder (mod), when it is $ne 0,$ since mod is simply repeated subtraction, i.e. $ abmod b, =, a - k b, =, a!-!b!-!b!-cdots! -!b.,$ Therefore $ ,nin S,$ $Rightarrow$ $ , (nbmod ell) = 0,,$ else it is in $, S,$ and smaller than $ ,ell,,$ contra minimality of $ ,ell.$
Remark $ $ In a nutshell, two applications of induction yield the following inferences
$begineqnarrayrm S closed under bf subtraction &:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf mod = remainder = repeated subtraction \
&:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf gcd = repeated mod (Euclid's algorithm) endeqnarray$
This yields Bezout's GCD identity: the set $ ,S,$ of integers of form $ ,a_1,x_1 + cdots + a_n x_n, x_iin mathbb Z,,$ is closed under subtraction so Lemma $Rightarrow$ every positive $ ,kin S,$ is divisible by $ ,d = $ least positive $ in S.,$ Therefore $ ,a_iin S$ $,Rightarrow,$ $ dmid a_i,,$ i.e. $ ,d,$ is a common divisor of all $ ,a_i,,$ necessarily the greatest such because $ cmid a_i$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cmid d = a_!,x_1!+!cdots!+!a_nx_n$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cle d.,$ When interpreted constructively, this yields the extended Euclidean algorithm for the gcd.
add a comment |
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
22
down vote
accepted
Consider, for instance, the statment: every $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ can be written as a product of prime numbers (including the case in which there's a single prime number appearing only once). Suppose otherwise. Then there would be a smallest $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ that would not be possible the express as a product of prime numbers. In particular, this implies that $n$ cannot be a prime number. Since $n$ is also not $1$, it can be written as $atimes b$, where $a,bin2,3,ldots,n-1$. But, since $n$ is the smallest counterexample, neither $a$ nor $b$ are counterexamples and therefore both of them can be written as a product of prime numbers. But then $n(=atimes b)$ can be written in such a way too.
add a comment |
up vote
22
down vote
accepted
Consider, for instance, the statment: every $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ can be written as a product of prime numbers (including the case in which there's a single prime number appearing only once). Suppose otherwise. Then there would be a smallest $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ that would not be possible the express as a product of prime numbers. In particular, this implies that $n$ cannot be a prime number. Since $n$ is also not $1$, it can be written as $atimes b$, where $a,bin2,3,ldots,n-1$. But, since $n$ is the smallest counterexample, neither $a$ nor $b$ are counterexamples and therefore both of them can be written as a product of prime numbers. But then $n(=atimes b)$ can be written in such a way too.
add a comment |
up vote
22
down vote
accepted
up vote
22
down vote
accepted
Consider, for instance, the statment: every $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ can be written as a product of prime numbers (including the case in which there's a single prime number appearing only once). Suppose otherwise. Then there would be a smallest $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ that would not be possible the express as a product of prime numbers. In particular, this implies that $n$ cannot be a prime number. Since $n$ is also not $1$, it can be written as $atimes b$, where $a,bin2,3,ldots,n-1$. But, since $n$ is the smallest counterexample, neither $a$ nor $b$ are counterexamples and therefore both of them can be written as a product of prime numbers. But then $n(=atimes b)$ can be written in such a way too.
Consider, for instance, the statment: every $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ can be written as a product of prime numbers (including the case in which there's a single prime number appearing only once). Suppose otherwise. Then there would be a smallest $ninmathbbNsetminus1$ that would not be possible the express as a product of prime numbers. In particular, this implies that $n$ cannot be a prime number. Since $n$ is also not $1$, it can be written as $atimes b$, where $a,bin2,3,ldots,n-1$. But, since $n$ is the smallest counterexample, neither $a$ nor $b$ are counterexamples and therefore both of them can be written as a product of prime numbers. But then $n(=atimes b)$ can be written in such a way too.
answered Nov 17 at 19:16
José Carlos Santos
139k18111203
139k18111203
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
13
down vote
Such a proof will often go as follows.
- Assume for contradiction that there is a counterexample to $P$ within some well-ordered set $X$.
- Consider the (certainly non-empty) set of all $X$ which are counterexamples to $P$. This set has a least element (that's what it means to be a well-order), so…
- Consider the smallest counterexample.
- Show that you can find a smaller counterexample.
- Contradiction, so there can't have been any counterexamples to $P$ after all.
- Therefore $P$ is true.
add a comment |
up vote
13
down vote
Such a proof will often go as follows.
- Assume for contradiction that there is a counterexample to $P$ within some well-ordered set $X$.
- Consider the (certainly non-empty) set of all $X$ which are counterexamples to $P$. This set has a least element (that's what it means to be a well-order), so…
- Consider the smallest counterexample.
- Show that you can find a smaller counterexample.
- Contradiction, so there can't have been any counterexamples to $P$ after all.
- Therefore $P$ is true.
add a comment |
up vote
13
down vote
up vote
13
down vote
Such a proof will often go as follows.
- Assume for contradiction that there is a counterexample to $P$ within some well-ordered set $X$.
- Consider the (certainly non-empty) set of all $X$ which are counterexamples to $P$. This set has a least element (that's what it means to be a well-order), so…
- Consider the smallest counterexample.
- Show that you can find a smaller counterexample.
- Contradiction, so there can't have been any counterexamples to $P$ after all.
- Therefore $P$ is true.
Such a proof will often go as follows.
- Assume for contradiction that there is a counterexample to $P$ within some well-ordered set $X$.
- Consider the (certainly non-empty) set of all $X$ which are counterexamples to $P$. This set has a least element (that's what it means to be a well-order), so…
- Consider the smallest counterexample.
- Show that you can find a smaller counterexample.
- Contradiction, so there can't have been any counterexamples to $P$ after all.
- Therefore $P$ is true.
answered Nov 17 at 19:16
Patrick Stevens
27.8k52873
27.8k52873
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
Assume the $sqrt2$ is rational then there are whole numbers $(a,b)$ such that $sqrt2=a/b$ and $a$ is the smallest number with this property but then we find that $a/2, b/2$ are also whole numbers with this property. So there is a smaller example.
I think this must be the example people are the most familiar with and it's a kind of infinite descent even though we often don't refer to it as such.
1
In this proof how do we know that $a/2$, $b/2$ are also whole numbers? (I'm probably missing something obvious.)
– LarsH
Nov 18 at 0:50
1
It isn't obvious but it is infamous. I can't find it for you now because I am out to dinner. But you can find by looking up the classic proof regarding the irrationality of square root of 2. Its in Bertrand Russell's history of western philosophy...
– Mason
Nov 18 at 0:57
3
@LarsH ny squaring the equation and wiggling it a bit you can prove that a is even, and then that b is also even.
– Dan M.
Nov 18 at 2:29
Here are the details
– Mason
Nov 18 at 2:38
1
@LarsH We have $2 = a^2/b^2$ hence $2b^2 = a^2$ from which: $a^2$ is even, hence $a$ is even, hence $a^2$ is a multiple of 4, hence $b^2=a^2/2$ is even, hence $b$ is even. So, both $a,b$ are even.
– chi
2 days ago
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
Assume the $sqrt2$ is rational then there are whole numbers $(a,b)$ such that $sqrt2=a/b$ and $a$ is the smallest number with this property but then we find that $a/2, b/2$ are also whole numbers with this property. So there is a smaller example.
I think this must be the example people are the most familiar with and it's a kind of infinite descent even though we often don't refer to it as such.
1
In this proof how do we know that $a/2$, $b/2$ are also whole numbers? (I'm probably missing something obvious.)
– LarsH
Nov 18 at 0:50
1
It isn't obvious but it is infamous. I can't find it for you now because I am out to dinner. But you can find by looking up the classic proof regarding the irrationality of square root of 2. Its in Bertrand Russell's history of western philosophy...
– Mason
Nov 18 at 0:57
3
@LarsH ny squaring the equation and wiggling it a bit you can prove that a is even, and then that b is also even.
– Dan M.
Nov 18 at 2:29
Here are the details
– Mason
Nov 18 at 2:38
1
@LarsH We have $2 = a^2/b^2$ hence $2b^2 = a^2$ from which: $a^2$ is even, hence $a$ is even, hence $a^2$ is a multiple of 4, hence $b^2=a^2/2$ is even, hence $b$ is even. So, both $a,b$ are even.
– chi
2 days ago
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
up vote
9
down vote
Assume the $sqrt2$ is rational then there are whole numbers $(a,b)$ such that $sqrt2=a/b$ and $a$ is the smallest number with this property but then we find that $a/2, b/2$ are also whole numbers with this property. So there is a smaller example.
I think this must be the example people are the most familiar with and it's a kind of infinite descent even though we often don't refer to it as such.
Assume the $sqrt2$ is rational then there are whole numbers $(a,b)$ such that $sqrt2=a/b$ and $a$ is the smallest number with this property but then we find that $a/2, b/2$ are also whole numbers with this property. So there is a smaller example.
I think this must be the example people are the most familiar with and it's a kind of infinite descent even though we often don't refer to it as such.
answered Nov 17 at 19:20
Mason
1,6501325
1,6501325
1
In this proof how do we know that $a/2$, $b/2$ are also whole numbers? (I'm probably missing something obvious.)
– LarsH
Nov 18 at 0:50
1
It isn't obvious but it is infamous. I can't find it for you now because I am out to dinner. But you can find by looking up the classic proof regarding the irrationality of square root of 2. Its in Bertrand Russell's history of western philosophy...
– Mason
Nov 18 at 0:57
3
@LarsH ny squaring the equation and wiggling it a bit you can prove that a is even, and then that b is also even.
– Dan M.
Nov 18 at 2:29
Here are the details
– Mason
Nov 18 at 2:38
1
@LarsH We have $2 = a^2/b^2$ hence $2b^2 = a^2$ from which: $a^2$ is even, hence $a$ is even, hence $a^2$ is a multiple of 4, hence $b^2=a^2/2$ is even, hence $b$ is even. So, both $a,b$ are even.
– chi
2 days ago
add a comment |
1
In this proof how do we know that $a/2$, $b/2$ are also whole numbers? (I'm probably missing something obvious.)
– LarsH
Nov 18 at 0:50
1
It isn't obvious but it is infamous. I can't find it for you now because I am out to dinner. But you can find by looking up the classic proof regarding the irrationality of square root of 2. Its in Bertrand Russell's history of western philosophy...
– Mason
Nov 18 at 0:57
3
@LarsH ny squaring the equation and wiggling it a bit you can prove that a is even, and then that b is also even.
– Dan M.
Nov 18 at 2:29
Here are the details
– Mason
Nov 18 at 2:38
1
@LarsH We have $2 = a^2/b^2$ hence $2b^2 = a^2$ from which: $a^2$ is even, hence $a$ is even, hence $a^2$ is a multiple of 4, hence $b^2=a^2/2$ is even, hence $b$ is even. So, both $a,b$ are even.
– chi
2 days ago
1
1
In this proof how do we know that $a/2$, $b/2$ are also whole numbers? (I'm probably missing something obvious.)
– LarsH
Nov 18 at 0:50
In this proof how do we know that $a/2$, $b/2$ are also whole numbers? (I'm probably missing something obvious.)
– LarsH
Nov 18 at 0:50
1
1
It isn't obvious but it is infamous. I can't find it for you now because I am out to dinner. But you can find by looking up the classic proof regarding the irrationality of square root of 2. Its in Bertrand Russell's history of western philosophy...
– Mason
Nov 18 at 0:57
It isn't obvious but it is infamous. I can't find it for you now because I am out to dinner. But you can find by looking up the classic proof regarding the irrationality of square root of 2. Its in Bertrand Russell's history of western philosophy...
– Mason
Nov 18 at 0:57
3
3
@LarsH ny squaring the equation and wiggling it a bit you can prove that a is even, and then that b is also even.
– Dan M.
Nov 18 at 2:29
@LarsH ny squaring the equation and wiggling it a bit you can prove that a is even, and then that b is also even.
– Dan M.
Nov 18 at 2:29
Here are the details
– Mason
Nov 18 at 2:38
Here are the details
– Mason
Nov 18 at 2:38
1
1
@LarsH We have $2 = a^2/b^2$ hence $2b^2 = a^2$ from which: $a^2$ is even, hence $a$ is even, hence $a^2$ is a multiple of 4, hence $b^2=a^2/2$ is even, hence $b$ is even. So, both $a,b$ are even.
– chi
2 days ago
@LarsH We have $2 = a^2/b^2$ hence $2b^2 = a^2$ from which: $a^2$ is even, hence $a$ is even, hence $a^2$ is a multiple of 4, hence $b^2=a^2/2$ is even, hence $b$ is even. So, both $a,b$ are even.
– chi
2 days ago
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
A fundamental example in number theory is descent by (Euclidean) division with remainder (or, equivalently, by repeated subtraction), as in the following basic result.
Lemma $ $ Let $,S,$ be a nonempty set of positive integers that is closed under subtraction $> 0,,$ i.e. for all $ ,n,min S, ,$ $ n > m Rightarrow n-m, in, S.,$ Then the least $ :ellin S,$ divides every element of $, S.$
Proof $bf 1, $ If not there is a least nonmultiple $ ,nin S,,$ contra $ ,n-ell in S,$ is a nonmultiple of $ ,ell.$
Proof $bf 2, , S,$ closed under subtraction $ ,Rightarrow,S,$ closed under remainder (mod), when it is $ne 0,$ since mod is simply repeated subtraction, i.e. $ abmod b, =, a - k b, =, a!-!b!-!b!-cdots! -!b.,$ Therefore $ ,nin S,$ $Rightarrow$ $ , (nbmod ell) = 0,,$ else it is in $, S,$ and smaller than $ ,ell,,$ contra minimality of $ ,ell.$
Remark $ $ In a nutshell, two applications of induction yield the following inferences
$begineqnarrayrm S closed under bf subtraction &:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf mod = remainder = repeated subtraction \
&:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf gcd = repeated mod (Euclid's algorithm) endeqnarray$
This yields Bezout's GCD identity: the set $ ,S,$ of integers of form $ ,a_1,x_1 + cdots + a_n x_n, x_iin mathbb Z,,$ is closed under subtraction so Lemma $Rightarrow$ every positive $ ,kin S,$ is divisible by $ ,d = $ least positive $ in S.,$ Therefore $ ,a_iin S$ $,Rightarrow,$ $ dmid a_i,,$ i.e. $ ,d,$ is a common divisor of all $ ,a_i,,$ necessarily the greatest such because $ cmid a_i$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cmid d = a_!,x_1!+!cdots!+!a_nx_n$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cle d.,$ When interpreted constructively, this yields the extended Euclidean algorithm for the gcd.
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
A fundamental example in number theory is descent by (Euclidean) division with remainder (or, equivalently, by repeated subtraction), as in the following basic result.
Lemma $ $ Let $,S,$ be a nonempty set of positive integers that is closed under subtraction $> 0,,$ i.e. for all $ ,n,min S, ,$ $ n > m Rightarrow n-m, in, S.,$ Then the least $ :ellin S,$ divides every element of $, S.$
Proof $bf 1, $ If not there is a least nonmultiple $ ,nin S,,$ contra $ ,n-ell in S,$ is a nonmultiple of $ ,ell.$
Proof $bf 2, , S,$ closed under subtraction $ ,Rightarrow,S,$ closed under remainder (mod), when it is $ne 0,$ since mod is simply repeated subtraction, i.e. $ abmod b, =, a - k b, =, a!-!b!-!b!-cdots! -!b.,$ Therefore $ ,nin S,$ $Rightarrow$ $ , (nbmod ell) = 0,,$ else it is in $, S,$ and smaller than $ ,ell,,$ contra minimality of $ ,ell.$
Remark $ $ In a nutshell, two applications of induction yield the following inferences
$begineqnarrayrm S closed under bf subtraction &:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf mod = remainder = repeated subtraction \
&:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf gcd = repeated mod (Euclid's algorithm) endeqnarray$
This yields Bezout's GCD identity: the set $ ,S,$ of integers of form $ ,a_1,x_1 + cdots + a_n x_n, x_iin mathbb Z,,$ is closed under subtraction so Lemma $Rightarrow$ every positive $ ,kin S,$ is divisible by $ ,d = $ least positive $ in S.,$ Therefore $ ,a_iin S$ $,Rightarrow,$ $ dmid a_i,,$ i.e. $ ,d,$ is a common divisor of all $ ,a_i,,$ necessarily the greatest such because $ cmid a_i$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cmid d = a_!,x_1!+!cdots!+!a_nx_n$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cle d.,$ When interpreted constructively, this yields the extended Euclidean algorithm for the gcd.
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
up vote
1
down vote
A fundamental example in number theory is descent by (Euclidean) division with remainder (or, equivalently, by repeated subtraction), as in the following basic result.
Lemma $ $ Let $,S,$ be a nonempty set of positive integers that is closed under subtraction $> 0,,$ i.e. for all $ ,n,min S, ,$ $ n > m Rightarrow n-m, in, S.,$ Then the least $ :ellin S,$ divides every element of $, S.$
Proof $bf 1, $ If not there is a least nonmultiple $ ,nin S,,$ contra $ ,n-ell in S,$ is a nonmultiple of $ ,ell.$
Proof $bf 2, , S,$ closed under subtraction $ ,Rightarrow,S,$ closed under remainder (mod), when it is $ne 0,$ since mod is simply repeated subtraction, i.e. $ abmod b, =, a - k b, =, a!-!b!-!b!-cdots! -!b.,$ Therefore $ ,nin S,$ $Rightarrow$ $ , (nbmod ell) = 0,,$ else it is in $, S,$ and smaller than $ ,ell,,$ contra minimality of $ ,ell.$
Remark $ $ In a nutshell, two applications of induction yield the following inferences
$begineqnarrayrm S closed under bf subtraction &:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf mod = remainder = repeated subtraction \
&:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf gcd = repeated mod (Euclid's algorithm) endeqnarray$
This yields Bezout's GCD identity: the set $ ,S,$ of integers of form $ ,a_1,x_1 + cdots + a_n x_n, x_iin mathbb Z,,$ is closed under subtraction so Lemma $Rightarrow$ every positive $ ,kin S,$ is divisible by $ ,d = $ least positive $ in S.,$ Therefore $ ,a_iin S$ $,Rightarrow,$ $ dmid a_i,,$ i.e. $ ,d,$ is a common divisor of all $ ,a_i,,$ necessarily the greatest such because $ cmid a_i$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cmid d = a_!,x_1!+!cdots!+!a_nx_n$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cle d.,$ When interpreted constructively, this yields the extended Euclidean algorithm for the gcd.
A fundamental example in number theory is descent by (Euclidean) division with remainder (or, equivalently, by repeated subtraction), as in the following basic result.
Lemma $ $ Let $,S,$ be a nonempty set of positive integers that is closed under subtraction $> 0,,$ i.e. for all $ ,n,min S, ,$ $ n > m Rightarrow n-m, in, S.,$ Then the least $ :ellin S,$ divides every element of $, S.$
Proof $bf 1, $ If not there is a least nonmultiple $ ,nin S,,$ contra $ ,n-ell in S,$ is a nonmultiple of $ ,ell.$
Proof $bf 2, , S,$ closed under subtraction $ ,Rightarrow,S,$ closed under remainder (mod), when it is $ne 0,$ since mod is simply repeated subtraction, i.e. $ abmod b, =, a - k b, =, a!-!b!-!b!-cdots! -!b.,$ Therefore $ ,nin S,$ $Rightarrow$ $ , (nbmod ell) = 0,,$ else it is in $, S,$ and smaller than $ ,ell,,$ contra minimality of $ ,ell.$
Remark $ $ In a nutshell, two applications of induction yield the following inferences
$begineqnarrayrm S closed under bf subtraction &:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf mod = remainder = repeated subtraction \
&:Rightarrow:&rm S closed under bf gcd = repeated mod (Euclid's algorithm) endeqnarray$
This yields Bezout's GCD identity: the set $ ,S,$ of integers of form $ ,a_1,x_1 + cdots + a_n x_n, x_iin mathbb Z,,$ is closed under subtraction so Lemma $Rightarrow$ every positive $ ,kin S,$ is divisible by $ ,d = $ least positive $ in S.,$ Therefore $ ,a_iin S$ $,Rightarrow,$ $ dmid a_i,,$ i.e. $ ,d,$ is a common divisor of all $ ,a_i,,$ necessarily the greatest such because $ cmid a_i$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cmid d = a_!,x_1!+!cdots!+!a_nx_n$ $Rightarrow$ $ ,cle d.,$ When interpreted constructively, this yields the extended Euclidean algorithm for the gcd.
answered Nov 17 at 22:37
Bill Dubuque
206k29189621
206k29189621
add a comment |
add a comment |
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3002706%2fwhat-is-an-example-of-a-proof-by-minimal-counterexample%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
3
If there aren't any counterexamples, the theorem is true, and we're done, so it's only the case where there is a counterexample that we have to deal with. This method of proof goes back (at least) to Fermat, who called it "proof by infinite descent." Google that, and you'll find lots of examples.
– saulspatz
Nov 17 at 19:14
Related: matheducators.stackexchange.com/questions/10021/…
– Ethan Bolker
Nov 17 at 19:25
1
Any uneven natural number is prime. Counterexample 9 = 3*3.
– Uwe
Nov 17 at 21:52
Are you referring to things like i.stack.imgur.com/RxeiH.png?
– forest
2 days ago
2
(If I understand correctly) "proof by minimal counterexample" proves that a minimal counterexample does not exist (wikipedia), and the 2 comments above are not correct.
– user202729
2 days ago