What is the relevance of KripkeâÂÂs modal argument against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names?
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by KripkeâÂÂs modal argument against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names. IâÂÂm guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at âÂÂrealâ philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.
Consider, for example, the sentence âÂÂAristotle is the best student of Plato.âÂÂ
From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description âÂÂthe best student of Platoâ is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out âÂÂthe best student of PlatoâÂÂ, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.
What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.
The text I am reading, Colin McGinnâÂÂs The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to KripkeâÂÂs modal argument though this is not one of them.
Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.
EDIT
To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.
philosophy-of-language
add a comment |Â
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by KripkeâÂÂs modal argument against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names. IâÂÂm guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at âÂÂrealâ philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.
Consider, for example, the sentence âÂÂAristotle is the best student of Plato.âÂÂ
From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description âÂÂthe best student of Platoâ is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out âÂÂthe best student of PlatoâÂÂ, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.
What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.
The text I am reading, Colin McGinnâÂÂs The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to KripkeâÂÂs modal argument though this is not one of them.
Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.
EDIT
To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.
philosophy-of-language
See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
â Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago
@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
add a comment |Â
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by KripkeâÂÂs modal argument against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names. IâÂÂm guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at âÂÂrealâ philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.
Consider, for example, the sentence âÂÂAristotle is the best student of Plato.âÂÂ
From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description âÂÂthe best student of Platoâ is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out âÂÂthe best student of PlatoâÂÂ, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.
What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.
The text I am reading, Colin McGinnâÂÂs The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to KripkeâÂÂs modal argument though this is not one of them.
Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.
EDIT
To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.
philosophy-of-language
I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by KripkeâÂÂs modal argument against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names. IâÂÂm guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at âÂÂrealâ philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.
Consider, for example, the sentence âÂÂAristotle is the best student of Plato.âÂÂ
From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description âÂÂthe best student of Platoâ is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out âÂÂthe best student of PlatoâÂÂ, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.
What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.
The text I am reading, Colin McGinnâÂÂs The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to KripkeâÂÂs modal argument though this is not one of them.
Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against FregeâÂÂs description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.
EDIT
To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.
philosophy-of-language
philosophy-of-language
edited 41 mins ago
asked 3 hours ago
Nick R
2,927926
2,927926
See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
â Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago
@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
add a comment |Â
See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
â Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago
@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
â Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago
See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
â Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago
@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
add a comment |Â
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
up vote
2
down vote
If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".
We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".
You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.
Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
â Nick R
59 mins ago
add a comment |Â
up vote
1
down vote
According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.
To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.
Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.
The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.
Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
â Eliran
2 hours ago
May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
â Eliran
1 hour ago
That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
â Nick R
1 hour ago
 |Â
show 2 more comments
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
2
down vote
If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".
We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".
You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.
Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
â Nick R
59 mins ago
add a comment |Â
up vote
2
down vote
If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".
We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".
You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.
Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
â Nick R
59 mins ago
add a comment |Â
up vote
2
down vote
up vote
2
down vote
If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".
We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".
You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.
If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".
We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".
You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.
answered 1 hour ago
Adam
786
786
Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
â Nick R
59 mins ago
add a comment |Â
Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
â Nick R
59 mins ago
Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
â Nick R
59 mins ago
Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
â Nick R
59 mins ago
add a comment |Â
up vote
1
down vote
According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.
To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.
Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.
The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.
Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
â Eliran
2 hours ago
May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
â Eliran
1 hour ago
That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
â Nick R
1 hour ago
 |Â
show 2 more comments
up vote
1
down vote
According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.
To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.
Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.
The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.
Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
â Eliran
2 hours ago
May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
â Eliran
1 hour ago
That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
â Nick R
1 hour ago
 |Â
show 2 more comments
up vote
1
down vote
up vote
1
down vote
According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.
To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.
Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.
The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.
According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.
To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.
Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.
The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.
edited 1 hour ago
answered 2 hours ago
Eliran
4,08621133
4,08621133
Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
â Eliran
2 hours ago
May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
â Eliran
1 hour ago
That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
â Nick R
1 hour ago
 |Â
show 2 more comments
Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
â Eliran
2 hours ago
May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
â Eliran
1 hour ago
That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
â Nick R
1 hour ago
Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
â Eliran
2 hours ago
@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
â Eliran
2 hours ago
May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
â Nick R
2 hours ago
@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
â Eliran
1 hour ago
@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
â Eliran
1 hour ago
That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
â Nick R
1 hour ago
That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
â Nick R
1 hour ago
 |Â
show 2 more comments
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f56608%2fwhat-is-the-relevance-of-kripke-s-modal-argument-against-frege-s-description-the%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
â Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago
@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
â Nick R
2 hours ago