What is the relevance of Kripke’s modal argument against Frege’s description theory of names?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
2
down vote

favorite












I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by Kripke’s modal argument against Frege’s description theory of names. I’m guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at “real” philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.



Consider, for example, the sentence “Aristotle is the best student of Plato.”



From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description “the best student of Plato” is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out “the best student of Plato”, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.



What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.



The text I am reading, Colin McGinn’s The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to Kripke’s modal argument though this is not one of them.



Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against Frege’s description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.




EDIT



To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.










share|improve this question























  • See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    2 hours ago










  • @MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago














up vote
2
down vote

favorite












I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by Kripke’s modal argument against Frege’s description theory of names. I’m guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at “real” philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.



Consider, for example, the sentence “Aristotle is the best student of Plato.”



From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description “the best student of Plato” is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out “the best student of Plato”, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.



What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.



The text I am reading, Colin McGinn’s The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to Kripke’s modal argument though this is not one of them.



Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against Frege’s description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.




EDIT



To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.










share|improve this question























  • See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    2 hours ago










  • @MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago












up vote
2
down vote

favorite









up vote
2
down vote

favorite











I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by Kripke’s modal argument against Frege’s description theory of names. I’m guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at “real” philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.



Consider, for example, the sentence “Aristotle is the best student of Plato.”



From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description “the best student of Plato” is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out “the best student of Plato”, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.



What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.



The text I am reading, Colin McGinn’s The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to Kripke’s modal argument though this is not one of them.



Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against Frege’s description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.




EDIT



To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.










share|improve this question















I am trying to learn a bit about the philosophy of language and I am puzzled by Kripke’s modal argument against Frege’s description theory of names. I’m guessing, and guessing is what I mean since I have never been any good at “real” philosophy, that Kripke is arguing that identifying a name with a description requires necessity and sufficiency, just as formal logic demands for equivalence.



Consider, for example, the sentence “Aristotle is the best student of Plato.”



From the point of view of possible worlds, it is clear the the description “the best student of Plato” is contingent in the sense that, as we traverse our modal space picking out “the best student of Plato”, we will not necessarily pick out Aristotle in all possible worlds. Thus, the description fails the necessity requirement of (modal) logical equivalence. Fair enough.



What I am puzzled by is why this is relevant. Natural language is not logical. For example, it includes all sorts of nuance, idiomatic expression, etc., all of which can be used in effective communication. In our world Aristotle is the best student of Plato and therefore this description correctly and uniquely identifies Aristotle - i.e., it is necessary and sufficient in our world.



The text I am reading, Colin McGinn’s The Philosophy of Language - The Classics Explained, highlights many objections to Kripke’s modal argument though this is not one of them.



Q: What is the relevance of possible worlds in arguing against Frege’s description theory of names? Frege's theory is not modal, so why is Kripke modal argument against it relevant.




EDIT



To be clear, McGinn begins his account of Kripke's theory by outlining what he calls Kripke's Modal Argument and Epistemic Argument against Frege's description theory of names. This is done as a direct argument against Frege. My problem with this is that Kripke is using a different logic than Frege, so it is not so much a direct argument against Frege as an alternative theory to Frege's theory.







philosophy-of-language






share|improve this question















share|improve this question













share|improve this question




share|improve this question








edited 41 mins ago

























asked 3 hours ago









Nick R

2,927926




2,927926











  • See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    2 hours ago










  • @MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago
















  • See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
    – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
    2 hours ago










  • @MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago















See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
– Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago




See also Reference : Descriptivist Theories.
– Mauro ALLEGRANZA
2 hours ago












@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
– Nick R
2 hours ago




@MauroALLEGRANZA Thanks for the reference. I've had a quick look and it is interesting to read about the direct reference theory put forward by Marcus which appears to bypass such modal issues.
– Nick R
2 hours ago










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
2
down vote













If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".



We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".



You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.






share|improve this answer




















  • Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
    – Nick R
    59 mins ago

















up vote
1
down vote













According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.



To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.



Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.



The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.






share|improve this answer






















  • Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago











  • @NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
    – Eliran
    2 hours ago











  • May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago










  • @NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
    – Eliran
    1 hour ago











  • That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
    – Nick R
    1 hour ago











Your Answer







StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "265"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: false,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: null,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f56608%2fwhat-is-the-relevance-of-kripke-s-modal-argument-against-frege-s-description-the%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes








2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
2
down vote













If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".



We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".



You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.






share|improve this answer




















  • Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
    – Nick R
    59 mins ago














up vote
2
down vote













If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".



We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".



You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.






share|improve this answer




















  • Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
    – Nick R
    59 mins ago












up vote
2
down vote










up vote
2
down vote









If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".



We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".



You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.






share|improve this answer












If your question is "why is Kripke allowed to appeal to our modal intuitions about the way the world could have been in?", then I think the answer is because he's putting forward a theory of how we actually use names, and that his theory of names is closer to how we actually use names than the descriptivist theory. Since it's a theory about language and its use by us, he's allowed to appeal to intuitions about what we would say if we were in different circumstances or the world were different in some way. And this is just what he means by a "possible world".



We would still use the name "Aristotle" to refer to the same man Aristotle we do in this actual world, even if he hadn't done those things we typically associate with him. If someone else had become the best student of Plato, we wouldn't then say "okay, now that person is now Aristotle".



You could insist that this is how you mean a name, as an abbreviated description. But for any given name you'd be saying some things that are strange to speakers of your language. Like in the example of Aristotle, you would have to say whatever is the greatest student of Plato, that's what "Aristotle" refers to.







share|improve this answer












share|improve this answer



share|improve this answer










answered 1 hour ago









Adam

786




786











  • Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
    – Nick R
    59 mins ago
















  • Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
    – Nick R
    59 mins ago















Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
– Nick R
59 mins ago




Thanks. This is useful in that it helps me to better understand the role of possible worlds in the philosophy of language - so +1 for that. Kripke may provide a better theory than Frege's theory but that does not appear to justify its status as a direct argument against Frege since it is using an alternative logic.
– Nick R
59 mins ago










up vote
1
down vote













According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.



To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.



Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.



The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.






share|improve this answer






















  • Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago











  • @NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
    – Eliran
    2 hours ago











  • May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago










  • @NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
    – Eliran
    1 hour ago











  • That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
    – Nick R
    1 hour ago















up vote
1
down vote













According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.



To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.



Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.



The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.






share|improve this answer






















  • Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago











  • @NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
    – Eliran
    2 hours ago











  • May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago










  • @NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
    – Eliran
    1 hour ago











  • That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
    – Nick R
    1 hour ago













up vote
1
down vote










up vote
1
down vote









According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.



To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.



Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.



The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.






share|improve this answer














According to the description theory, the meaning of names is given by a list of descriptions. For example, the name "Aristotle" just means "the best student of Plato & the teacher of Alexander the Great & ...", and the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle because that is the person that satisfies all these descriptions.



To this Kripke objects that Aristotle could have failed to satisfy some of these descriptions while still remaining Aristotle. That is, the name "Aristotle" picks out Aristotle even in possible worlds where he isn't the best student of Plato, or where he doesn't even become a philosopher, etc.



Instead, Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. That is, they refer to the same object in all possible worlds in which that object exists. According to the description theory, on the other hand, names are not rigid designators.



The SEP entry on names explains both the description theory and Kripke's argument against it in more detail.







share|improve this answer














share|improve this answer



share|improve this answer








edited 1 hour ago

























answered 2 hours ago









Eliran

4,08621133




4,08621133











  • Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago











  • @NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
    – Eliran
    2 hours ago











  • May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago










  • @NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
    – Eliran
    1 hour ago











  • That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
    – Nick R
    1 hour ago

















  • Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago











  • @NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
    – Eliran
    2 hours ago











  • May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
    – Nick R
    2 hours ago










  • @NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
    – Eliran
    1 hour ago











  • That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
    – Nick R
    1 hour ago
















Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
– Nick R
2 hours ago





Thanks for your answer, and yes I was being a bit sloppy using "description theory" rather than "description theory of names". I shall update my question accordingly. It is not clear to me how this answers the question of relevance of possible worlds. Why should it matter that, in some possible world, Aristotle was a carpenter rather than a philosopher.
– Nick R
2 hours ago













@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
– Eliran
2 hours ago





@NickR I did mention possible worlds in my answer, but maybe that part wasn't clear enough. Can you say a little more about what you're asking? Maybe I'll be able to address that better.
– Eliran
2 hours ago













May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
– Nick R
2 hours ago




May I compliment my caveat that I have never been any good at "real" philosophy with the addition that I also have mild dyslexia so my reading skills are not brilliant. I am asking that, since "the best student of Plato" is both necessary and sufficient in our world, why should it be relevant that it is not necessary and sufficient in all possible worlds.
– Nick R
2 hours ago












@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
– Eliran
1 hour ago





@NickR That's because the description theory purports to give the meaning of names. If names mean the same as descriptions then they have to refer to the same things in all possible worlds. Otherwise, names and descriptions don't have the same meaning. (That's the idea behind the argument, anyway.)
– Eliran
1 hour ago













That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
– Nick R
1 hour ago





That makes sense from Kripke's point of view. However, as far as I am aware, Frege's theory is not modal, so why should modal arguments against it carry any weight. Kripke seems to be recasting Frege's argument as modal.
– Nick R
1 hour ago


















 

draft saved


draft discarded















































 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f56608%2fwhat-is-the-relevance-of-kripke-s-modal-argument-against-frege-s-description-the%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Popular posts from this blog

How to check contact read email or not when send email to Individual?

Displaying single band from multi-band raster using QGIS

How many registers does an x86_64 CPU actually have?