Understanding sheaves on a $2$-element set
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
$begingroup$
I'm working through the Geometry of Schemes and wanted some clarification for an exercise.
Exercise I-5 considers a two-element set $X=0,1$ with the discrete topology and asks the reader to find the relations between the objects of a sheaf (of abelian groups) on $X$.
If we let $mathcalF$ be the sheaf, then it's clear that $mathcalF(emptyset)$ is the trivial group and that we have a commutative diagram of restrictions from $mathcalF(0)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(0)$, and from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$.
By the sheaf axiom, it seems like for any $sinmathcalF(0)$ and $tinmathcalF(1)$, $s$ and $t$ restricted to the intersection, $emptyset$, must be the same, so there is some unique section in $mathcalF(0,1)$ that restricts to $s$ and $t$.
What does this say about $mathcalF(0,1)$? I'm guessing it's related to the fiber product, but I'm not particularly well-versed in category theory. Also, how does this generalize to sheaves over different categories?
algebraic-geometry category-theory sheaf-theory
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I'm working through the Geometry of Schemes and wanted some clarification for an exercise.
Exercise I-5 considers a two-element set $X=0,1$ with the discrete topology and asks the reader to find the relations between the objects of a sheaf (of abelian groups) on $X$.
If we let $mathcalF$ be the sheaf, then it's clear that $mathcalF(emptyset)$ is the trivial group and that we have a commutative diagram of restrictions from $mathcalF(0)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(0)$, and from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$.
By the sheaf axiom, it seems like for any $sinmathcalF(0)$ and $tinmathcalF(1)$, $s$ and $t$ restricted to the intersection, $emptyset$, must be the same, so there is some unique section in $mathcalF(0,1)$ that restricts to $s$ and $t$.
What does this say about $mathcalF(0,1)$? I'm guessing it's related to the fiber product, but I'm not particularly well-versed in category theory. Also, how does this generalize to sheaves over different categories?
algebraic-geometry category-theory sheaf-theory
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
If you haven't already, it is easy to prove that $mathcal F(varnothing)$ is always the terminal object for any topological space $X$ for sheaves of sets. You can also prove that if this is true for sheaves of sets, then it's also true for sheaves of any essentially algebraic structure.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 5 at 21:22
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I'm working through the Geometry of Schemes and wanted some clarification for an exercise.
Exercise I-5 considers a two-element set $X=0,1$ with the discrete topology and asks the reader to find the relations between the objects of a sheaf (of abelian groups) on $X$.
If we let $mathcalF$ be the sheaf, then it's clear that $mathcalF(emptyset)$ is the trivial group and that we have a commutative diagram of restrictions from $mathcalF(0)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(0)$, and from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$.
By the sheaf axiom, it seems like for any $sinmathcalF(0)$ and $tinmathcalF(1)$, $s$ and $t$ restricted to the intersection, $emptyset$, must be the same, so there is some unique section in $mathcalF(0,1)$ that restricts to $s$ and $t$.
What does this say about $mathcalF(0,1)$? I'm guessing it's related to the fiber product, but I'm not particularly well-versed in category theory. Also, how does this generalize to sheaves over different categories?
algebraic-geometry category-theory sheaf-theory
$endgroup$
I'm working through the Geometry of Schemes and wanted some clarification for an exercise.
Exercise I-5 considers a two-element set $X=0,1$ with the discrete topology and asks the reader to find the relations between the objects of a sheaf (of abelian groups) on $X$.
If we let $mathcalF$ be the sheaf, then it's clear that $mathcalF(emptyset)$ is the trivial group and that we have a commutative diagram of restrictions from $mathcalF(0)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$, from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(0)$, and from $mathcalF(0,1)$ to $mathcalF(emptyset)$.
By the sheaf axiom, it seems like for any $sinmathcalF(0)$ and $tinmathcalF(1)$, $s$ and $t$ restricted to the intersection, $emptyset$, must be the same, so there is some unique section in $mathcalF(0,1)$ that restricts to $s$ and $t$.
What does this say about $mathcalF(0,1)$? I'm guessing it's related to the fiber product, but I'm not particularly well-versed in category theory. Also, how does this generalize to sheaves over different categories?
algebraic-geometry category-theory sheaf-theory
algebraic-geometry category-theory sheaf-theory
edited Feb 5 at 18:06
Asaf Karagila♦
305k33435766
305k33435766
asked Feb 5 at 16:26
whethamwhetham
16117
16117
1
$begingroup$
If you haven't already, it is easy to prove that $mathcal F(varnothing)$ is always the terminal object for any topological space $X$ for sheaves of sets. You can also prove that if this is true for sheaves of sets, then it's also true for sheaves of any essentially algebraic structure.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 5 at 21:22
add a comment |
1
$begingroup$
If you haven't already, it is easy to prove that $mathcal F(varnothing)$ is always the terminal object for any topological space $X$ for sheaves of sets. You can also prove that if this is true for sheaves of sets, then it's also true for sheaves of any essentially algebraic structure.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 5 at 21:22
1
1
$begingroup$
If you haven't already, it is easy to prove that $mathcal F(varnothing)$ is always the terminal object for any topological space $X$ for sheaves of sets. You can also prove that if this is true for sheaves of sets, then it's also true for sheaves of any essentially algebraic structure.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 5 at 21:22
$begingroup$
If you haven't already, it is easy to prove that $mathcal F(varnothing)$ is always the terminal object for any topological space $X$ for sheaves of sets. You can also prove that if this is true for sheaves of sets, then it's also true for sheaves of any essentially algebraic structure.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 5 at 21:22
add a comment |
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
In this case, $mathcalF(0,1)$ is just the direct product of the groups
$mathcalF(0)$ and $mathcalF(1)$.
This commutative diagram has to be a pullback
$requireAMScd$
beginCD
mathcalF(0,1) @>>> mathcalF(1)\
@V V V @VV V\
mathcalF(0) @>>> mathcalF(emptyset)=0
endCD
but as the southeast corner is trivial, the northwest group
is the direct product of the other corners, and the nontrivial
maps are the projections from a direct product to its factors.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
How do we know that $calF(0,1)$ (with the maps downwards and to the right) is universal?
$endgroup$
– whetham
Feb 6 at 16:27
$begingroup$
@whetham The diagram in the answer is essentially a particular instance of the sheaf condition. A pullback can be formulated as an equalizer of products.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 6 at 19:27
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);
else
createEditor();
);
function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);
);
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3101364%2funderstanding-sheaves-on-a-2-element-set%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
In this case, $mathcalF(0,1)$ is just the direct product of the groups
$mathcalF(0)$ and $mathcalF(1)$.
This commutative diagram has to be a pullback
$requireAMScd$
beginCD
mathcalF(0,1) @>>> mathcalF(1)\
@V V V @VV V\
mathcalF(0) @>>> mathcalF(emptyset)=0
endCD
but as the southeast corner is trivial, the northwest group
is the direct product of the other corners, and the nontrivial
maps are the projections from a direct product to its factors.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
How do we know that $calF(0,1)$ (with the maps downwards and to the right) is universal?
$endgroup$
– whetham
Feb 6 at 16:27
$begingroup$
@whetham The diagram in the answer is essentially a particular instance of the sheaf condition. A pullback can be formulated as an equalizer of products.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 6 at 19:27
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In this case, $mathcalF(0,1)$ is just the direct product of the groups
$mathcalF(0)$ and $mathcalF(1)$.
This commutative diagram has to be a pullback
$requireAMScd$
beginCD
mathcalF(0,1) @>>> mathcalF(1)\
@V V V @VV V\
mathcalF(0) @>>> mathcalF(emptyset)=0
endCD
but as the southeast corner is trivial, the northwest group
is the direct product of the other corners, and the nontrivial
maps are the projections from a direct product to its factors.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
How do we know that $calF(0,1)$ (with the maps downwards and to the right) is universal?
$endgroup$
– whetham
Feb 6 at 16:27
$begingroup$
@whetham The diagram in the answer is essentially a particular instance of the sheaf condition. A pullback can be formulated as an equalizer of products.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 6 at 19:27
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In this case, $mathcalF(0,1)$ is just the direct product of the groups
$mathcalF(0)$ and $mathcalF(1)$.
This commutative diagram has to be a pullback
$requireAMScd$
beginCD
mathcalF(0,1) @>>> mathcalF(1)\
@V V V @VV V\
mathcalF(0) @>>> mathcalF(emptyset)=0
endCD
but as the southeast corner is trivial, the northwest group
is the direct product of the other corners, and the nontrivial
maps are the projections from a direct product to its factors.
$endgroup$
In this case, $mathcalF(0,1)$ is just the direct product of the groups
$mathcalF(0)$ and $mathcalF(1)$.
This commutative diagram has to be a pullback
$requireAMScd$
beginCD
mathcalF(0,1) @>>> mathcalF(1)\
@V V V @VV V\
mathcalF(0) @>>> mathcalF(emptyset)=0
endCD
but as the southeast corner is trivial, the northwest group
is the direct product of the other corners, and the nontrivial
maps are the projections from a direct product to its factors.
answered Feb 5 at 16:29
Lord Shark the UnknownLord Shark the Unknown
105k1160133
105k1160133
$begingroup$
How do we know that $calF(0,1)$ (with the maps downwards and to the right) is universal?
$endgroup$
– whetham
Feb 6 at 16:27
$begingroup$
@whetham The diagram in the answer is essentially a particular instance of the sheaf condition. A pullback can be formulated as an equalizer of products.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 6 at 19:27
add a comment |
$begingroup$
How do we know that $calF(0,1)$ (with the maps downwards and to the right) is universal?
$endgroup$
– whetham
Feb 6 at 16:27
$begingroup$
@whetham The diagram in the answer is essentially a particular instance of the sheaf condition. A pullback can be formulated as an equalizer of products.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 6 at 19:27
$begingroup$
How do we know that $calF(0,1)$ (with the maps downwards and to the right) is universal?
$endgroup$
– whetham
Feb 6 at 16:27
$begingroup$
How do we know that $calF(0,1)$ (with the maps downwards and to the right) is universal?
$endgroup$
– whetham
Feb 6 at 16:27
$begingroup$
@whetham The diagram in the answer is essentially a particular instance of the sheaf condition. A pullback can be formulated as an equalizer of products.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 6 at 19:27
$begingroup$
@whetham The diagram in the answer is essentially a particular instance of the sheaf condition. A pullback can be formulated as an equalizer of products.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 6 at 19:27
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3101364%2funderstanding-sheaves-on-a-2-element-set%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
1
$begingroup$
If you haven't already, it is easy to prove that $mathcal F(varnothing)$ is always the terminal object for any topological space $X$ for sheaves of sets. You can also prove that if this is true for sheaves of sets, then it's also true for sheaves of any essentially algebraic structure.
$endgroup$
– Derek Elkins
Feb 5 at 21:22